Talk:Empty function

Latest comment: 9 years ago by Quondum in topic alt definition

alt definition edit

What does the empty function evaluate to, for a particular set A?--ASL 00:51, 8 July 2007 (UTC)Reply

Since the empty function has an empty domain, the empty function doesn't "evaluate to" anything. Paul August 02:10, 8 July 2007 (UTC)Reply

I just wasn't used to defining a function in terms of a graph (which is a set, and therefore may be empty)--ASL 21:03, 8 July 2007 (UTC)Reply

The idea is not that the empty function is empty as a set, nor does it depend upon defining a function in terms of a graph. The idea is that the domain is empty, and it applies equally well using the informal definition of a function as a rule which associates each element of its domain with a unique element of its codomain. If you define a function as a graph then an empty function will, incidentally, also be empty as a set. However it is common to formally define a function as an ordered triple (A, B, G) where A (the domain) and B (the codomain) are sets and G (the graph) is a subset of A X B (the set of ordered pairs with first element in A and second element in B) satisfying the property that if (r, t) and (s, t) are in G then r = s. In this case, for any set B, (∅, B, ∅) is an empty function, but of course not the empty set. Notice this means that although there is only one empty set, there are an infinite number of empty functions, one for each set B. Paul August 16:29, 9 July 2007 (UTC)Reply
Interesting. I have as yet never encountered such a definition of function, it was always just a subset of the Cartesian product. What are the upsides? This definition clearly distinguishes between
 
 
 
such as f(x)=g(x)=h(x)=1 for every real x. Is there any situation where such a distinction is necessary or convenient? Because I can imagine situation where it would be convenient to use functions which differ only in codomain interchangeably. For example, there is a proof of Cantor-Bernstein theorem which utilizes a bijection created from injection by restricting its codomain to its range. Then, because by this definition those function would not be equal, the fact the created function was a bijection would not be trivial and had to be proved, which would approximately double the length of the proof. 109.73.215.142 (talk) 11:52, 20 December 2014 (UTC)Reply
Paul August's definition has the curious property that the domain may have elements that the function does not map to the codomain. I wonder whether this was the intent? It may be, since this gives the symmetry mentioned. But it would also mean that there is an empty function for every pairing between every domain–codomain pairing of sets, which is not what he stated. —Quondum 15:42, 20 December 2014 (UTC)Reply
I left out the condition that for each a in A, there exists a b in B such that (a, b) is in G (otherwise you have what's called a partial function). Paul August 12:53, 21 December 2014 (UTC)Reply
Well, I guess if one added a further restriction that each b in B, there exists an a in A such that (a, b) is in G, it would be neater (more symmetric). Then we're down to exactly one empty function ... I guess that there is no compelling reason to prefer any of the definitions. —Quondum 01:00, 22 December 2014 (UTC)Reply

Uniquely determined edit

For each set A, there is exactly one empty function

 

as

 ,

then

 

Simpler:

 ,

then

 ,


On the other hand, let

 ,

then