Von Neumann–Morgenstern utility theorem

In decision theory, the von Neumann–Morgenstern (VNM) utility theorem demonstrates that rational choice under uncertainty involves making decisions that take the form of maximizing the expected value of some cardinal utility function. This function is known as the von Neumann–Morgenstern utility function. The theorem forms the foundation of expected utility theory.

In 1947, John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern proved that any individual whose preferences satisfied four axioms has a utility function, where such an individual's preferences can be represented on an interval scale and the individual will always prefer actions that maximize expected utility.[1] That is, they proved that an agent is (VNM-)rational if and only if there exists a real-valued function u defined by possible outcomes such that every preference of the agent is characterized by maximizing the expected value of u, which can then be defined as the agent's VNM-utility (it is unique up to affine transformations i.e. adding a constant and multiplying by a positive scalar). No claim is made that the agent has a "conscious desire" to maximize u, only that u exists.

VNM-utility is a decision utility in that it is used to describe decisions. It is related, but not necessarily equivalent to, the utility of Bentham's utilitarianism.[2]

Set-up

edit

In the theorem, an individual agent is faced with options called lotteries. Given some mutually exclusive outcomes, a lottery is a scenario where each outcome will happen with a given probability, all probabilities summing to one. For example, for two outcomes A and B,

 

denotes a scenario where P(A) = 25% is the probability of A occurring and P(B) = 75% (and exactly one of them will occur). More generally, for a lottery with many possible outcomes Ai, we write:

 

with the sum of the  s equal to 1.

The outcomes in a lottery can themselves be lotteries between other outcomes, and the expanded expression is considered an equivalent lottery: 0.5(0.5A + 0.5B) + 0.5C = 0.25A + 0.25B + 0.50C.

If lottery M is preferred over lottery L, we write  , or equivalently,  . If the agent is indifferent between L and M, we write the indifference relation[3]   If M is either preferred over or viewed with indifference relative to L, we write  

The axioms

edit

The four axioms of VNM-rationality are completeness, transitivity, continuity, and independence. These axioms, apart from continuity, are often justified using the Dutch book theorems (whereas continuity is used to set aside lexicographic or infinitesimal utilities).

Completeness assumes that an individual has well defined preferences:

Axiom 1 (Completeness) For any lotteries   and  , either   or  .

(the individual must express some preference or indifference[4]). Note that this implies reflexivity.

Transitivity assumes that preferences are consistent across any three options:

Axiom 2 (Transitivity) If   and  , then  .

Continuity assumes that there is a "tipping point" between being better than and worse than a given middle option:

Axiom 3 (Continuity): If  , then there exists a probability   such that
 

where the notation on the left side refers to a situation in which L is received with probability p and N is received with probability (1–p).

Instead of continuity, an alternative axiom can be assumed that does not involve a precise equality, called the Archimedean property.[3] It says that any separation in preference can be maintained under a sufficiently small deviation in probabilities:

Axiom 3′ (Archimedean property): If  , then there exists a probability   such that
 

Only one of (3) or (3′) need to be assumed, and the other will be implied by the theorem.

Independence assumes that a preference holds independently of the probability of another outcome.

Axiom 4 (Independence): For any   and   (with the "irrelevant" part of the lottery underlined):
 

In other words, the probabilities involving   cancel out and don't affect our decision, because the probability of   is the same in both lotteries.

Note that the "only if" direction is necessary for the theorem to work. Without that, we have this counterexample: there are only two outcomes  , and the agent is indifferent on  , and strictly prefers all of them over  . With the "only if" direction, we can argue that   implies  , thus excluding this counterexample.

The independence axiom implies the axiom on reduction of compound lotteries:[5]

Axiom 4′ (Reduction of compound lotteries): For any lotteries   and any  ,
 
 

To see how Axiom 4 implies Axiom 4', set   in the expression in Axiom 4, and expand.

The theorem

edit

For any VNM-rational agent (i.e. satisfying axioms 1–4), there exists a function u which assigns to each outcome A a real number u(A) such that for any two lotteries,

 

where E(u(L)), or more briefly Eu(L) is given by

 

As such, u can be uniquely determined (up to adding a constant and multiplying by a positive scalar) by preferences between simple lotteries, meaning those of the form pA + (1 − p)B having only two outcomes. Conversely, any agent acting to maximize the expectation of a function u will obey axioms 1–4. Such a function is called the agent's von Neumann–Morgenstern (VNM) utility.

Proof sketch

edit

The proof is constructive: it shows how the desired function   can be built. Here we outline the construction process for the case in which the number of sure outcomes is finite.[6]: 132–134 

Suppose there are n sure outcomes,  . Note that every sure outcome can be seen as a lottery: it is a degenerate lottery in which the outcome is selected with probability 1. Hence, by the Completeness and Transitivity axioms, it is possible to order the outcomes from worst to best:

 

We assume that at least one of the inequalities is strict (otherwise the utility function is trivial—a constant). So  . We use these two extreme outcomes—the worst and the best—as the scaling unit of our utility function, and define:

  and  

For every probability  , define a lottery that selects the best outcome with probability   and the worst outcome otherwise:

 

Note that   and  .

By the Continuity axiom, for every sure outcome  , there is a probability   such that:

 

and

 

For every  , the utility function for outcome   is defined as

 

so the utility of every lottery   is the expectation of u:

 

To see why this utility function makes sense, consider a lottery  , which selects outcome   with probability  . But, by our assumption, the decision maker is indifferent between the sure outcome   and the lottery  . So, by the Reduction axiom, he is indifferent between the lottery   and the following lottery:

 
 
 

The lottery   is, in effect, a lottery in which the best outcome is won with probability  , and the worst outcome otherwise.

Hence, if  , a rational decision maker would prefer the lottery   over the lottery  , because it gives him a larger chance to win the best outcome.

Hence:

  if and only if  

Reaction

edit

Von Neumann and Morgenstern anticipated surprise at the strength of their conclusion. But according to them, the reason their utility function works is that it is constructed precisely to fill the role of something whose expectation is maximized:

"Many economists will feel that we are assuming far too much ... Have we not shown too much? ... As far as we can see, our postulates [are] plausible ... We have practically defined numerical utility as being that thing for which the calculus of mathematical expectations is legitimate." – VNM 1953, § 3.1.1 p.16 and § 3.7.1 p. 28[1]

Thus, the content of the theorem is that the construction of u is possible, and they claim little about its nature.

Consequences

edit

Automatic consideration of risk aversion

edit

It is often the case that a person, faced with real-world gambles with money, does not act to maximize the expected value of their dollar assets. For example, a person who only possesses $1000 in savings may be reluctant to risk it all for a 20% chance odds to win $10,000, even though

 

However, if the person is VNM-rational, such facts are automatically accounted for in their utility function u. In this example, we could conclude that

 

where the dollar amounts here really represent outcomes (cf. "value"), the three possible situations the individual could face. In particular, u can exhibit properties like u($1)+u($1) ≠ u($2) without contradicting VNM-rationality at all. This leads to a quantitative theory of monetary risk aversion.

Implications for the expected utility hypothesis

edit

In 1738, Daniel Bernoulli published a treatise[7] in which he posits that rational behavior can be described as maximizing the expectation of a function u, which in particular need not be monetary-valued, thus accounting for risk aversion. This is the expected utility hypothesis. As stated, the hypothesis may appear to be a bold claim. The aim of the expected utility theorem is to provide "modest conditions" (i.e. axioms) describing when the expected utility hypothesis holds, which can be evaluated directly and intuitively:

"The axioms should not be too numerous, their system is to be as simple and transparent as possible, and each axiom should have an immediate intuitive meaning by which its appropriateness may be judged directly. In a situation like ours this last requirement is particularly vital, in spite of its vagueness: we want to make an intuitive concept amenable to mathematical treatment and to see as clearly as possible what hypotheses this requires." – VNM 1953 § 3.5.2, p. 25[1]

As such, claims that the expected utility hypothesis does not characterize rationality must reject one of the VNM axioms. A variety of generalized expected utility theories have arisen, most of which drop or relax the independence axiom.

Implications for ethics and moral philosophy

edit

Because the theorem assumes nothing about the nature of the possible outcomes of the gambles, they could be morally significant events, for instance involving the life, death, sickness, or health of others. A von Neumann–Morgenstern rational agent is capable of acting with great concern for such events, sacrificing much personal wealth or well-being, and all of these actions will factor into the construction/definition of the agent's VNM-utility function. In other words, both what is naturally perceived as "personal gain", and what is naturally perceived as "altruism", are implicitly balanced in the VNM-utility function of a VNM-rational individual. Therefore, the full range of agent-focused to agent-neutral behaviors are possible with various VNM-utility functions[clarification needed].

If the utility of   is  , a von Neumann–Morgenstern rational agent must be indifferent between   and  . An agent-focused von Neumann–Morgenstern rational agent therefore cannot favor more equal, or "fair", distributions of utility between its own possible future selves.

Distinctness from other notions of utility

edit

Some utilitarian moral theories are concerned with quantities called the "total utility" and "average utility" of collectives, and characterize morality in terms of favoring the utility or happiness of others with disregard for one's own. These notions can be related to, but are distinct from, VNM-utility:

  • 1) VNM-utility is a decision utility:[2] it is that according to which one decides, and thus by definition cannot be something which one disregards.
  • 2) VNM-utility is not canonically additive across multiple individuals (see Limitations), so "total VNM-utility" and "average VNM-utility" are not immediately meaningful (some sort of normalization assumption is required).

The term E-utility for "experience utility" has been coined[2] to refer to the types of "hedonistic" utility like that of Bentham's greatest happiness principle. Since morality affects decisions, a VNM-rational agent's morals will affect the definition of its own utility function (see above). Thus, the morality of a VNM-rational agent can be characterized by correlation of the agent's VNM-utility with the VNM-utility, E-utility, or "happiness" of others, among other means, but not by disregard for the agent's own VNM-utility, a contradiction in terms.

Limitations

edit

Nested gambling

edit

Since if L and M are lotteries, then pL + (1 − p)M is simply "expanded out" and considered a lottery itself, the VNM formalism ignores what may be experienced as "nested gambling". This is related to the Ellsberg problem where people choose to avoid the perception of risks about risks. Von Neumann and Morgenstern recognized this limitation:

"...concepts like a specific utility of gambling cannot be formulated free of contradiction on this level. This may seem to be a paradoxical assertion. But anybody who has seriously tried to axiomatize that elusive concept, will probably concur with it." – VNM 1953 § 3.7.1, p. 28.[1]

Incomparability between agents

edit

Since for any two VNM-agents X and Y, their VNM-utility functions uX and uY are only determined up to additive constants and multiplicative positive scalars, the theorem does not provide any canonical way to compare the two. Hence expressions like uX(L) + uY(L) and uX(L) − uY(L) are not canonically defined, nor are comparisons like uX(L) < uY(L) canonically true or false. In particular, the aforementioned "total VNM-utility" and "average VNM-utility" of a population are not canonically meaningful without normalization assumptions.

Applicability to economics

edit

The expected utility hypothesis has been shown to have imperfect predictive accuracy in a set of lab based empirical experiments, such as the Allais paradox.

References and further reading

edit
  1. ^ a b c d Neumann, John von and Morgenstern, Oskar, Theory of Games and Economic Behavior. Princeton, NJ. Princeton University Press, 1953.
  2. ^ a b c Kahneman; Wakker; Sarin (1997). "Back to Bentham? Explorations of Experienced Utility". Quarterly Journal of Economics. 112 (2): 375–406. doi:10.1162/003355397555235. hdl:1765/23011.
  3. ^ a b Kreps, David M. Notes on the Theory of Choice. Westview Press (May 12, 1988), chapters 2 and 5.
  4. ^ Implicit in denoting indifference by equality are assertions like if   then  . To make such relations explicit in the axioms, Kreps (1988) chapter 2 denotes indifference by  , so it may be surveyed in brief for intuitive meaning.
  5. ^ EconPort, "Von Neumann–Morgenstern Expected Utility Theory" http://www.econport.org/content/handbook/decisions-uncertainty/basic/von.html
  6. ^ Keeney, Ralph L.; Raiffa, Howard (1993). Decisions with Multiple Objectives. ISBN 0-521-44185-4.
  7. ^ Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis or Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk