Jensen hierarchy

(Redirected from Rudimentary function)

In set theory, a mathematical discipline, the Jensen hierarchy or J-hierarchy is a modification of Gödel's constructible hierarchy, L, that circumvents certain technical difficulties that exist in the constructible hierarchy. The J-Hierarchy figures prominently in fine structure theory, a field pioneered by Ronald Jensen, for whom the Jensen hierarchy is named. Rudimentary functions describe a method for iterating through the Jensen hierarchy.

Definition edit

As in the definition of L, let Def(X) be the collection of sets definable with parameters over X:

 

The constructible hierarchy,   is defined by transfinite recursion. In particular, at successor ordinals,  .

The difficulty with this construction is that each of the levels is not closed under the formation of unordered pairs; for a given  , the set   will not be an element of  , since it is not a subset of  .

However,   does have the desirable property of being closed under Σ0 separation.[1]

Jensen's modification of the L hierarchy retains this property and the slightly weaker condition that  , but is also closed under pairing. The key technique is to encode hereditarily definable sets over   by codes; then   will contain all sets whose codes are in  .

Like  ,   is defined recursively. For each ordinal  , we define   to be a universal   predicate for  . We encode hereditarily definable sets as  , with  . Then set   and finally,  .

Properties edit

Each sublevel Jα, n is transitive and contains all ordinals less than or equal to αω + n. The sequence of sublevels is strictly ⊆-increasing in n, since a Σm predicate is also Σn for any n > m. The levels Jα will thus be transitive and strictly ⊆-increasing as well, and are also closed under pairing,  -comprehension and transitive closure. Moreover, they have the property that

 

as desired. (Or a bit more generally,  .[2])

The levels and sublevels are themselves Σ1 uniformly definable (i.e. the definition of Jα, n in Jβ does not depend on β), and have a uniform Σ1 well-ordering. Also, the levels of the Jensen hierarchy satisfy a condensation lemma much like the levels of Gödel's original hierarchy.

For any  , considering any   relation on  , there is a Skolem function for that relation that is itself definable by a   formula.[3]

Rudimentary functions edit

A rudimentary function is a Vn→V function (i.e. a finitary function accepting sets as arguments) that can be obtained from the following operations:[2]

  • F(x1, x2, ...) = xi is rudimentary (see projection function)
  • F(x1, x2, ...) = {xi, xj} is rudimentary
  • F(x1, x2, ...) = xixj is rudimentary
  • Any composition of rudimentary functions is rudimentary
  • zyG(z, x1, x2, ...) is rudimentary, where G is a rudimentary function

For any set M let rud(M) be the smallest set containing M∪{M} closed under the rudimentary functions. Then the Jensen hierarchy satisfies Jα+1 = rud(Jα).[2]

Projecta edit

Jensen defines  , the   projectum of  , as the largest   such that   is amenable for all  , and the   projectum of   is defined similarly. One of the main results of fine structure theory is that   is also the largest   such that not every   subset of   is (in the terminology of α-recursion theory)  -finite.[2]

Lerman defines the   projectum of   to be the largest   such that not every   subset of   is  -finite, where a set is   if it is the image of a function   expressible as   where   is  -recursive. In a Jensen-style characterization,   projectum of   is the largest   such that there is an   epimorphism from   onto  . There exists an ordinal   whose   projectum is  , but whose   projectum is   for all natural  . [4]

References edit

  1. ^ Wolfram Pohlers, Proof Theory: The First Step Into Impredicativity (2009) (p.247)
  2. ^ a b c d K. Devlin, An introduction to the fine structure of the constructible hierarchy (1974). Accessed 2022-02-26.
  3. ^ R. B. Jensen, The Fine Structure of the Constructible Hierarchy (1972), p.247. Accessed 13 January 2023.
  4. ^ S. G. Simpson, "Short course on admissible recursion theory". Appearing in Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics vol. 94, Generalized Recursion Theory II (1978), pp.355--390
  • Sy Friedman (2000) Fine Structure and Class Forcing, Walter de Gruyter, ISBN 3-11-016777-8