Theories of iterated inductive definitions

(Redirected from Buchholz's ID hierarchy)

In set theory and logic, Buchholz's ID hierarchy is a hierarchy of subsystems of first-order arithmetic. The systems/theories are referred to as "the formal theories of ν-times iterated inductive definitions". IDν extends PA by ν iterated least fixed points of monotone operators.

Definition edit

Original definition edit

The formal theory IDω (and IDν in general) is an extension of Peano Arithmetic, formulated in the language LID, by the following axioms:[1]

  •  
  •   for every LID-formula F(x)
  •  

The theory IDν with ν ≠ ω is defined as:

  •  
  •   for every LID-formula F(x) and each u < ν
  •  

Explanation / alternate definition edit

ID1 edit

A set   is called inductively defined if for some monotonic operator  ,  , where   denotes the least fixed point of  . The language of ID1,  , is obtained from that of first-order number theory,  , by the addition of a set (or predicate) constant IA for every X-positive formula A(X, x) in LN[X] that only contains X (a new set variable) and x (a number variable) as free variables. The term X-positive means that X only occurs positively in A (X is never on the left of an implication). We allow ourselves a bit of set-theoretic notation:

  •  
  •   means  
  • For two formulas   and  ,   means  .

Then ID1 contains the axioms of first-order number theory (PA) with the induction scheme extended to the new language as well as these axioms:

  •  
  •  

Where   ranges over all   formulas.

Note that   expresses that   is closed under the arithmetically definable set operator  , while   expresses that   is the least such (at least among sets definable in  ).

Thus,   is meant to be the least pre-fixed-point, and hence the least fixed point of the operator  .

IDν edit

To define the system of ν-times iterated inductive definitions, where ν is an ordinal, let   be a primitive recursive well-ordering of order type ν. We use Greek letters to denote elements of the field of  . The language of IDν,   is obtained from   by the addition of a binary predicate constant JA for every X-positive   formula   that contains at most the shown free variables, where X is again a unary (set) variable, and Y is a fresh binary predicate variable. We write   instead of  , thinking of x as a distinguished variable in the latter formula.

The system IDν is now obtained from the system of first-order number theory (PA) by expanding the induction scheme to the new language and adding the scheme   expressing transfinite induction along   for an arbitrary   formula   as well as the axioms:

  •  
  •  

where   is an arbitrary   formula. In   and   we used the abbreviation   for the formula  , where   is the distinguished variable. We see that these express that each  , for  , is the least fixed point (among definable sets) for the operator  . Note how all the previous sets  , for  , are used as parameters.

We then define  .

Variants edit

  -   is a weakened version of  . In the system of  , a set   is instead called inductively defined if for some monotonic operator  ,   is a fixed point of  , rather than the least fixed point. This subtle difference makes the system significantly weaker:  , while  .

  is   weakened even further. In  , not only does it use fixed points rather than least fixed points, and has induction only for positive formulas. This once again subtle difference makes the system even weaker:  , while  .

  is the weakest of all variants of  , based on W-types. The amount of weakening compared to regular iterated inductive definitions is identical to removing bar induction given a certain subsystem of second-order arithmetic.  , while  .

  is an "unfolding" strengthening of  . It is not exactly a first-order arithmetic system, but captures what one can get by predicative reasoning based on ν-times iterated generalized inductive definitions. The amount of increase in strength is identical to the increase from   to  :  , while  .

Results edit

  • Let ν > 0. If a ∈ T0 contains no symbol Dμ with ν < μ, then "a ∈ W0" is provable in IDν.
  • IDω is contained in  .
  • If a  -sentence   is provable in IDν, then there exists   such that  .
  • If the sentence A is provable in IDν for all ν < ω, then there exists k ∈ N such that  .

Proof-theoretic ordinals edit

  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of ID is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of IDν is equal to   .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   for   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   for   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   for   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of   is equal to  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of ID1 (the Bachmann-Howard ordinal) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of  ,  ,   and  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of W-IDω ( ) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of IDω (the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of  ,   and  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of ID<ω^ω ( ) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of  .
  • The proof-theoretic ordinal of ID<ε0 ( ) is also the proof-theoretic ordinal of   and  .

References edit

  1. ^ W. Buchholz, "An Independence Result for  ", Annals of Pure and Applied Logic vol. 33 (1987).