In order theory a better-quasi-ordering or bqo is a quasi-ordering that does not admit a certain type of bad array. Every better-quasi-ordering is a well-quasi-ordering.

Motivation edit

Though well-quasi-ordering is an appealing notion, many important infinitary operations do not preserve well-quasi-orderedness. An example due to Richard Rado illustrates this.[1] In a 1965 paper Crispin Nash-Williams formulated the stronger notion of better-quasi-ordering in order to prove that the class of trees of height ω is well-quasi-ordered under the topological minor relation.[2] Since then, many quasi-orderings have been proven to be well-quasi-orderings by proving them to be better-quasi-orderings. For instance, Richard Laver established Laver's theorem (previously a conjecture of Roland Fraïssé) by proving that the class of scattered linear order types is better-quasi-ordered.[3] More recently, Carlos Martinez-Ranero has proven that, under the proper forcing axiom, the class of Aronszajn lines is better-quasi-ordered under the embeddability relation.[4]

Definition edit

It is common in better-quasi-ordering theory to write   for the sequence   with the first term omitted. Write   for the set of finite, strictly increasing sequences with terms in  , and define a relation   on   as follows:   if there is   such that   is a strict initial segment of   and  . The relation   is not transitive.

A block   is an infinite subset of   that contains an initial segment[clarification needed] of every infinite subset of  . For a quasi-order  , a  -pattern is a function from some block   into  . A  -pattern   is said to be bad if  [clarification needed] for every pair   such that  ; otherwise   is good. A quasi-ordering   is called a better-quasi-ordering if there is no bad  -pattern.

In order to make this definition easier to work with, Nash-Williams defines a barrier to be a block whose elements are pairwise incomparable under the inclusion relation  . A  -array is a  -pattern whose domain is a barrier. By observing that every block contains a barrier, one sees that   is a better-quasi-ordering if and only if there is no bad  -array.

Simpson's alternative definition edit

Simpson introduced an alternative definition of better-quasi-ordering in terms of Borel functions  , where  , the set of infinite subsets of  , is given the usual product topology.[5]

Let   be a quasi-ordering and endow   with the discrete topology. A  -array is a Borel function   for some infinite subset   of  . A  -array   is bad if   for every  ;   is good otherwise. The quasi-ordering   is a better-quasi-ordering if there is no bad  -array in this sense.

Major theorems edit

Many major results in better-quasi-ordering theory are consequences of the Minimal Bad Array Lemma, which appears in Simpson's paper[5] as follows. See also Laver's paper,[6] where the Minimal Bad Array Lemma was first stated as a result. The technique was present in Nash-Williams' original 1965 paper.

Suppose   is a quasi-order.[clarification needed] A partial ranking   of   is a well-founded partial ordering of   such that  . For bad  -arrays (in the sense of Simpson)   and  , define:

 
 

We say a bad  -array   is minimal bad (with respect to the partial ranking  ) if there is no bad  -array   such that  . The definitions of   and   depend on a partial ranking   of  . The relation   is not the strict part of the relation  .

Theorem (Minimal Bad Array Lemma). Let   be a quasi-order equipped with a partial ranking and suppose   is a bad  -array. Then there is a minimal bad  -array   such that  .

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Rado, Richard (1954). "Partial well-ordering of sets of vectors". Mathematika. 1 (2): 89–95. doi:10.1112/S0025579300000565. MR 0066441.
  2. ^ Nash-Williams, C. St. J. A. (1965). "On well-quasi-ordering infinite trees". Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 61 (3): 697–720. Bibcode:1965PCPS...61..697N. doi:10.1017/S0305004100039062. ISSN 0305-0041. MR 0175814. S2CID 227358387.
  3. ^ Laver, Richard (1971). "On Fraïssé's Order Type Conjecture". The Annals of Mathematics. 93 (1): 89–111. doi:10.2307/1970754. JSTOR 1970754.
  4. ^ Martinez-Ranero, Carlos (2011). "Well-quasi-ordering Aronszajn lines". Fundamenta Mathematicae. 213 (3): 197–211. doi:10.4064/fm213-3-1. ISSN 0016-2736. MR 2822417.
  5. ^ a b Simpson, Stephen G. (1985). "BQO Theory and Fraïssé's Conjecture". In Mansfield, Richard; Weitkamp, Galen (eds.). Recursive Aspects of Descriptive Set Theory. The Clarendon Press, Oxford University Press. pp. 124–38. ISBN 978-0-19-503602-2. MR 0786122.
  6. ^ Laver, Richard (1978). "Better-quasi-orderings and a class of trees". In Rota, Gian-Carlo (ed.). Studies in foundations and combinatorics. Academic Press. pp. 31–48. ISBN 978-0-12-599101-8. MR 0520553.