Highest median voting rules

The highest median voting rules are a class of graded voting rules where the candidate with the highest median rating is elected.

The various highest median rules differ in their treatment of ties, i.e., the method of ranking the candidates with the same median rating.

Proponents of highest median rules argue that they provide the most faithful reflection of the voters' opinion. They note that as with other cardinal voting rules, highest medians are not subject to Arrow's impossibility theorem, and so can satisfy both independence of irrelevant alternatives and Pareto efficiency.

However, critics note that highest median rules violate participation and the Archimedean property; highest median rules can fail to elect a candidate almost-unanimously preferred over all other candidates.

Example

edit

As in score voting, voters rate candidates along a common scale, e.g.:

Excellent Very Good Good Fair Passable Inadequate Bad
Candidate A X
Candidate B X
Candidate C X
Candidate D X

An elector can give the same appreciation to several different candidates. A candidate not evaluated automatically receives the mention "Bad".[1]

Then, for each candidate, we calculate what percentage of voters assigned them each grade, e.g.:

Candidate Excellent Very Good Good Fair Passable Inadequate Bad TOTAL
A 5% 13% 21% 20% 9% 17% 15% 100%
B 5% 14% 19% 13% 13% 12% 24% 100%
C 4% 6% 10% 15% 16% 24% 25% 100%

This is presented graphically in the form of a cumulative histogram whose total corresponds to 100% of the votes cast:

 
An example of a cumulative histogram for a highest-median voting rule.

For each candidate, we then determine the majority (or median) grade (shown here in bold). This rule means that an absolute majority (more than 50%) of voters judge that a candidate deserves at least its majority grade, and that half or more (50% or more) of the electors judges that he deserves at the most its majority grade. Thus, the majority grade looks like a median.

If only one candidate has the highest median score, they are elected. Otherwise, highest median rules must invoke a tiebreaking procedure to choose between the candidates with the highest median grade.

Tiebreaking procedures

edit

When different candidates share the same median rating, a tie-breaking rule is required, analogous to interpolation. For discrete grading scales, the median is insensitive to changes in the data and highly sensitive to the choice of scale (as there are large "gaps" between ratings).

Most tie-breaking rules choose between tied candidates by comparing their relative shares of proponents (above-median grades) and opponents (below-median grades).[2] The share of proponents and opponents are represented by   and   respectively, while their share of median grades is written as  .

  • Bucklin's rule orders candidates by (one minus) the number of opponents.[3] Anti-Bucklin reverses this (choosing the candidate with the highest share of proponents).
  • The majority judgment considers the candidate who is closest to having a rating other than its median and breaks the tie based on that rating.[2]
  • The typical judgment ranks candidates by the number of proponents minus the number of opponents,[2] i.e.  .
  • The central judgment divides the typical judgment by the total number of proponents and opponents.
  • Continuous Bucklin voting or Graduated Majority Judgment (GMJ), also called the usual judgment,[2] ranks candidates by the share of their median grades needed to reach 50% support.
    • This is equivalent to using a linear interpolation between the current score and the next-highest score.
    • Compared to typical judgment, this leads to a more prominent score difference when the median share is low; in other words, candidates who are more "polarizing" receive more extreme evaluations.

Example

edit
 
Example of an election where each choice (or candidate) A-F wins according to one of the tie-breaking rules: typical, central, graduated majority, majority, Bucklin, and anti-Bucklin.[2]

The example in the following table shows a six-way tied rating, where each alternative wins under one of the rules mentioned above. (All scores apart from Bucklin/anti-Bucklin are scaled to fall in  to allow for interpreting them as interpolations between the next-highest and next-lowest scores.)

Candidate Against For Diff Central Nearest GMJ
A 15% 30% 15% 17% 30% 14%
B 4% 11% 7% 23% 11% 4%
C 27% 40% 13% 10% 40% 20%
D 43% 45% 2% 1% 45% 8%
E 3% 0% -3% -50% -3% -2%
F 49% 46% -3% -2% -49% -30%
Formula            

Advantages and Disadvantages

edit

Advantages

edit

Common to cardinal voting methods

edit

Cardinal voting systems allow voters to provide much more information than ranked-choice ballots (so long as there are enough categories); in addition to allowing voters to specify which of two candidates they prefer, cardinal ballots allow them to express how strongly they prefer such candidates.[4] Voters can choose between a wide variety of options for rating candidates, allowing for nuanced judgments of quality.[4][5]

Because highest median methods ask voters to evaluate candidates rather than rank them, they escape Arrow's impossibility theorem, and satisfy both unanimity and independence of irrelevant alternatives.[6] However, highest medians fail the slightly stronger near-unanimity criterion (see #Disadvantages).

Several candidates belonging to a similar political faction can participate in the election without helping or hurting each other, as highest median methods satisfy independence from irrelevant alternatives:[6] Adding candidates does not change the ranking of previous candidates. In other words, if a group ranks A higher than B when choosing between A and B, they should not rank that B higher than A when choosing between A, B, and C.

Unique to highest medians

edit

The most commonly-cited advantage of highest median rules over their mean-based counterparts is they minimize the number of voters who have an incentive to be dishonest.[4] Voters with weak preferences in particular will not have much incentive to give candidates very high or very low scores. On the other hand, all voters in a score voting system have an incentive to exaggerate, which in theory would lead to de facto approval voting for a large share of the electorate most voters will only give the highest or lowest score to every candidate).

Disadvantages

edit

Participation failure

edit

Highest median rules violate the participation criterion; in other words, a candidate may lose because they have "too many supporters."

In the example below, notice how adding the two ballots labeled "+" causes A (the initial winner) to lose to B:

+ + New Median Old Median
A 9 9 9 6 5 3 0
B 9 7 7 7 4 2 0
C 9 0 0 4 3 2 0

It can be proven that score voting (i.e. choosing highest mean instead of highest median) is the unique voting system satisfying the participation criterion, Archimedean property, and independence of irrelevant alternatives, as a corollary of the VNM utility theorem.[7]

Archimedean property

edit

Highest median rules violate the Archimedean property; informally, the Archimedean property says that if "99.999...%" of voters prefer Alice to Bob, Alice should defeat Bob. As shown below, it is possible for Alice to defeat Bob in an election, even if only one voter thinks Bob is better than Alice, and a very large number of voters (up to 100%) give Alice a higher rating:

Ballots (Bolded medians)
# ballots Alice Bob Charlie
Many 100/100 52/100 0/100
1 50/100 51/100 1/100
Many 49/100 0/100 100/100

In this election, Bob has the highest median score (51) and defeats Alice, even though every voter except one (perhaps Bob himself) thinks Alice is a better candidate. This is true no matter how many voters there are. As a result, even a single voter's weak preferences can override the strong preferences of the rest of the electorate.

The above example restricted to candidates Alice and Bob also serves as an example of highest median rules failing the majority criterion, although highest medians can pass the majority criterion with normalized ballots (i.e. ballots scaled to use the whole 0-100 range). However, normalization cannot recover the Archimedean criterion.

Feasibility

edit

A poll of French voters found a majority would be opposed to implementing majority judgment, but a majority would support conducting elections by score voting.[8][9][better source needed]

edit
  • Cardinal voting systems are similar to highest median methods, but determine winners using a statistic other than the median; the most common of these is score voting, which uses the mean.
  • Approval voting corresponds to the degenerate case where there are only two possible ratings: approval and disapproval. In this case, all tie-breaking rules are equivalent.[10]

See also

edit

Further reading

edit
  • Baujard, Antoinette; Gavrel, Frédéric; Igersheim, Herrade; Laslier, Jean-François; Lebon, Isabelle (September 2017). "How voters use grade scales in evaluative voting" (PDF). European Journal of Political Economy. 55: 14–28. doi:10.1016/j.ejpoleco.2017.09.006. ISSN 0176-2680.

References

edit
  1. ^ "Le jugement majoritaire". lechoixcommun.fr (in French). Archived from the original on 2021-02-04. Retrieved 2021-02-10.
  2. ^ a b c d e Fabre, Adrien (2020). "Tie-breaking the Highest Median: Alternatives to the Majority Judgment" (PDF). Social Choice and Welfare. 56: 101–124. doi:10.1007/s00355-020-01269-9. ISSN 0176-1714. S2CID 226196615.
  3. ^ Collective decisions and voting: the potential for public choice, Nicolaus Tideman, 2006, p. 204
  4. ^ a b c Balinski, Michel (2019). "Réponse à des critiques du jugement majoritaire". Revue Économique. 70 (4): 589–610. doi:10.3917/reco.704.0589. S2CID 199348869 – via CAIRN.
  5. ^ Balinski, Michel; Laraki, Rida (2012). "Jugement majoritaire versus vote majoritaire". Revue Française d'Économie. 27: 33 – via CAIRN.
  6. ^ a b Leray, Marjolaine; Hogg, Carol. "A little more democracy? Cartoons by Marjolaine Leray on the topic of Majority Judgment" (PDF). Le Choix commun.
  7. ^ Balinski, Michel; Laraki, Rida (2011). Majority Judgment: Measuring, Ranking, and Electing (1 ed.). The MIT Press. pp. 285–287. ISBN 978-0-262-01513-4.
  8. ^ "RangeVoting.org - What voters want". www.rangevoting.org. Retrieved 2023-12-30.
  9. ^ https://www.rangevoting.org/Sondageopinionway2012FR.pdf [bare URL PDF]
  10. ^ Brams, Steven; Fishburn, Peter (1978). "Approval Voting". American Political Science Review. 72 (3): 831–847. doi:10.2307/1955105. JSTOR 1955105. S2CID 251092061.