Anaximenes of Miletus (/ˌænækˈsɪməˌniːz/; Greek: Ἀναξιμένης ὁ Μιλήσιος; c. 586/585 – c. 526/525 BC) was an Ancient Greek, Pre-Socratic philosopher from Miletus in Asia Minor (modern-day Turkey), active in the 6th century BC.
Anaximenes of Miletus | |
---|---|
![]() Anaximenes of Miletus as imaginatively depicted, wearing a tainia, in a 16th century engraving from Girolamo Olgiati. | |
Born | c. 586/585 BC |
Died | c. 526/525 BC (aged c. 60) Miletus |
Era | Pre-Socratic philosophy |
Region | Western philosophy |
School | Ionian/Milesian school |
Main interests | Metaphysics Natural philosophy |
Notable ideas | Air is the arche Matter changes through rarefaction and condensation |
Influences | |
Influenced |
He was the last of the three philosophers of the Milesian School, considered the first philosophers of the Western world. Anaximenes is best known and identified as a younger friend or student of Anaximander, who was himself taught by the very first philosopher Thales, one of the Seven Sages of Greece. Thales proposed all was made of water; Anaximander proposed all was made of apeiron or something indefinite rather than something specific, and Anaximenes proposed all was made of air. More condensed air made for colder, denser objects and more rarefied air made for hotter, lighter objects.
The life and views of Anaximenes remain obscure as none of his work has been preserved, and he is only known through comments about him made by later writers. His cosmological views seem similar to his two Milesian predecessors. Anaximenes thought that the earth was flat and tilted, with the shape of a table (or trapezoid), and floated on air. The other celestial bodies were also flat and supported by air.
BiographyEdit
Anaximenes the son of Eurystratos was from Miletus, an Ionian Greek town on the western coast of Asia Minor or Anatolia, settled near the mouth of the Maeander River.[1][2] He is the third philosopher in the Western tradition, after Anaximander, who came after Thales, who was one of the Seven Sages of Greece.[3] He is given the number 13 in the standard Diels–Kranz numbering.
His dates are lost to history. Anaximenes is considered by Aristotle's follower Theophrastus (as relayed by Simplicius) to have been the younger pupil of Anaximander,[4] and he is also considered old enough to have influenced Pythagoras.[1][5][6]
According to Diogenes Laertius, in Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, a principal source for the history of ancient Greek philosophy, the chronologist Apollodorus of Athens estimated Anaximenes' lifespan by surmising he flourished during the same time period as when the Persian king Cyrus the Great defeated the Lydian king Croesus; at the Battle of Thymbra and subsequent Siege of Sardis in 546 BC.[7][8][9][a] The typical age for one's acme of 40 years old is assumed for when one was 'fluorishing' placing his birth at 586 BC.
Other inferences suggest a similar time period: the Eclipse of Thales on May 28, 585 BC, interrupting a battle in a war between the Medes and the Lydians, is used to date when Thales fluorished. Further it is figured Anaximenes was born around when Thales 'fluorished' and 'fluorished' when Thales died.[7][11][12]
According to classicist John Burnet, he was considered in his time a more important figure than his teacher Anaximander.[5][13] Some of Anaximenes' writings are referenced during the Hellenistic Age, but no record of these documents currently exist.[b] Further details of his life and philosophical views are obscure as none of his work has been preserved, and he is only known through fragments and interpretations of him made by later writers and polemicists, such as Aristotle.[15]
Air as the ArcheEdit
According to Aristotle, and his follower Theophrastus, each philosopher of the Milesian School was a material monist who sought to discover the arche; the one, underlying basis of everything.[4][16][c] Aristotle called the first philosophers physiologoi (φυσιολόγοι), natural philosophers.[18] Anaximenes thought air was the primary substance that held the universe together.[15] Or literally aer, which may also include mist or vapor.[8]
Anaximenes views were seen to reconcile the views of his two predecessors, Thales and Anaximander. Air as the arche had the feature of being one (like with Thales, who believed it was water), and infinite (like with Anaximander, who thought it was apeiron), but determinate, like Thales and unlike Anaximander.[17] It was also seen as the substance most capable of change, for he also saw air as always in motion.[19]
As well as specific, infinite and dynamic, he believed that air was divine.[2][4][19][d] He identified air with the "breath of life" and thus the soul as well as the air in the atmosphere.[8][22][23][e] Only a single, sentence-long quote by Anaximenes survives: "Just as our soul...being air holds us together, so pneuma and air encompass [and guard] the whole world."[25][26][27] This is the first extant source to use the word pneuma ("breath").[28]
Condensation and rarefactionEdit
Anaximenes seemed to base his conclusions on naturally observable phenomena in the water cycle, the processes of rarefaction and condensation.[29] Anaximenes attributed cold/wet air to be due to condensation, hot/dry air to be due to rarefaction.[2][14][30] This can be classically illustrated by blowing on one's hand with pursed lips and feeling cold air, or with an open mouth and feeling warm air.[31]
Anaximenes figured this difference in the degree of condensation and density of air further produced all matter.[22] According to Anaximenes, the "loose",[24] spread-out, infinite air was condensed to wind, then formed into clouds, which condensed further to produce rain, snow, and other forms of precipitation.[22][24] The process continued until the air was condensed or felted enough to be tangible and form solids like dirt and ultimately stones. By contrast, just as water evaporates into air, air was further rarefied into fire or light.[8]
While Thales and Anaximander also recognized transitions in states of matter, Anaximenes was the first to associate the qualitative change in hot/dry and cold/wet pairings with the quantitative density of a single material.[32][33] Though noticing this anticipation of science is only a retrodiction, "for him density was a quantitative notion only in the weakest sense".[34]
CosmologyEdit
Anaximenes also used air to explain the nature of the earth and the surrounding celestial bodies. In the beginning of the world, air condensed to create the flat surface of the earth, which he said was shaped like a table (or trapezoid),[f] and was tilted.[36][37][38] According to Aristotle in On the Heavens, Anaximenes thought the world stayed still by floating like a lid covering the air beneath it.[39][40][g]
He said the Sun floated on air, as like a broad leaf.[43] The moon also floated on air.[2] He thought of stars as similar to nails that are stuck in a transparent shell.[44][8] In keeping with the prevailing view of stars as balls of fire in the sky, Anaximenes proposed that the earth let out an exhalation of air that rarefied, ignited and became the stars.[45] While the sun is similarly described as being aflame, Anaximenes thought it is not composed of rarefied air like the stars, but rather of earth like the moon. According to Pseudo-Plutarch, Anaximenes thought its burning comes not from its composition but rather from its rapid motion.[40][28][46]
In his theory, according to the Christian polemicist Hippolytus in Refutation of All Heresies, when the sun sets it does not pass under the earth, but is merely obscured by higher parts of the earth as it circles around and becomes more distant.[2][38] Aristotle also relates that "many of the ancient cosmologists" believed this.[47] Hippolytus likens the motion of the sun and the other celestial bodies around the earth to the way that a cap may be turned around the head.[48][49]
Anaximenes believed that the sky was a dome and this dome the outer frontier of the earth.[50] Day and night are caused by celestial bodies being carried North until they are no longer seen. There is evidence that suggests Anaximenes may have been the first person to distinguish between planets and fixed stars.[8] The Anaximenes crater on the Moon is named in his honor.
Weather and other natural phenomenaEdit
Anaximenes provided causes for other natural phenomena on the earth as well. Earthquakes, he asserted, were the result either of lack of moisture, which causes the earth to break apart because of how parched it is, or of superabundance of water, which also causes cracks in the earth.[51] In either case the earth becomes weakened by its cracks, so that hills collapse and cause earthquakes. Lightning is similarly caused by the violent separation of clouds by the wind, creating a bright, fire-like flash. Rainbows, on the other hand, are formed when densely compressed air is touched by the rays of the sun.[49][52]
Death and legacyEdit
The traditional age to guess for his death is at 60 years old.[1] He could not have lived well into the 5th Century BC, for he was presumably getting old, and in response to the Ionian Revolt, Miletus was captured by the Persian army of Darius the Great in 494 BC.[24][28]
Influence on philosophyEdit
Pre-Socratic philosophyEdit
The theories of Anaximenes were likely influential upon later Presocratic philosophers. Perhaps because of the aforementioned capture of Miletus in 494 BC, philosophy seemed to shift focus to Italy before coming back to Asia Minor.[24][53]
Similarly to Anaximenes, the Pythagoreans in Italy, according to Aristotle, believed the world breathed; that there was "boundless breath" which was "outside the heavens, and … was inhaled by the world".[54][55] Xenophanes claimed the rainbow is a cloud, which on one interpretation is a response to Anaximenes idea that a rainbow is from light reflected off of clouds.[56] Xenophanes theory that the arche is earth and water can also be seen as his response to Anaximenes.[57]
The cosmology of Anaxagoras back in Asia Minor shared many similarities with that of Anaximenes, and was likely influenced by it,[19][58][59] while the atomists Democritus and Leucippus adopted Anaximenes' view that the world was flat.[5][39][60] Diogenes of Apollonia attempted to amalgamate the theories of Anaximenes with those of Anaxagoras.[61] He took up the view of Anaximenes' that air was the arche, and that all substances were the result of the condensation and rarefaction of air.[5][62]
Plato and AristotleEdit
In the Timaeus, Plato favorably mentions Anaximenes's theory of matter and its seven states from stone to fire. Plato treats Anaximenes as a kind of philosopher of process rather than a material monist, as Aristotle portrays him. From this perspective, Anaximenes can be seen as a forerunner of Heraclitus and ultimately Plato, moreso than of Diogenes of Apollonia.[63][64][65] Plato may be referencing Anaximenes in the Phaedo when he states "And so one man makes the earth stay below the heavens by putting a vortex about it, and another regards the earth as a flat trough supported on a foundation of air."[28][66]
Aristotle is the oldest extant writer to reference Anaximenes by name.[65] Sometimes however he also seems to merely allude to him, e. g. "Diogenes, however, as also some others, identified soul with air. Air, they thought, is made up of the finest particles and is the first principle."[67][68] Aristotle in Generation of Animals calls pneuma the "vital heat".[69][70][71]
StoicsEdit
The Stoics believed pneuma to be a mix of the elements fire and air. In a view reminiscent of Anaximenes, Chrysippus believed pneuma is what moved the body, and what held everything together.[72][73] It existed in men as nous, in animals as psyche, in plants as physis, and in inanimate objects as hexis, or qualities and dispositions. "Whiteness" for example, was ultimately air.[74]
NotesEdit
- ^ Cyrus the Great would a few years later defeat Babylon, ending the Babylonian captivity.[10]
- ^ According to Diogenes Laertius he wrote straightforwardly; in the "pure unmixed Ionian dialect."[1][14]
- ^ They were arguably being anachronistic by imposing the peculiarly Aristotelian notion of substance on to earlier philosophy.[17]
- ^ Thales said everything was "full of gods".[20][21]
- ^ While Anaximenes was a pagan philosopher, it is interesting to note the Old Testament features a similar image of the breath of life in the founding of the world and creation of man: Genesis 2:7.[24]
- ^ The word trapezoid (τραπεζοειδῆ) comes from the Greek trapeza meaning "table" and -oeides meaning "shaped." So this term can ambiguously refer to something that is table-shaped, or trapezoid-shaped. Several writers therefore contend what was meant about Anaximenes was not a world shaped like a flat circle, but like a trapezoid.[35]
- ^ This view of the earth has been analogized to that of a disc or frisbee.[41][42]
ReferencesEdit
CitationsEdit
- ^ a b c d Laërtius 1925, p. 57-58 (DK13A1)
- ^ a b c d e Hippolytus, Refutation of All Heresies 1.7.1 - 1.7.6 (DK13A7)
- ^ Hussey 2005, p. 33
- ^ a b c Simplicius, On Aristotle, Physics p. 151, 24 (DK 13A5)
- ^ a b c d Burnet 1930, p. 78-79.
- ^ Kerferd, G. B. “The Date of Anaximenes.” Museum Helveticum, vol. 11, no. 2, 1954, pp. 117–21. JSTOR, http://www.jstor.org/stable/24812026. Accessed 28 Apr. 2023.
- ^ a b A.A. Mosshammer, 'Geometrical proportion and the chronological method of Apollodorus', Transactions of the American Philological Association 106 (1976) 291-306
- ^ a b c d e f Dye, James (2014), "Anaximenes of Miletus", Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers, Springer New York, pp. 74–75, doi:10.1007/978-1-4419-9917-7_49, ISBN 9781441999160
- ^ Lindberg 2007, p. 28.
- ^ Augustine, City of God, Book 18
- ^ Kirk, Raven & Schofield 1957, p. 143
- ^ Burnet 1930, p. 72.
- ^ see also Barnes 1982, p. 39
- ^ a b Guthrie 1962, p. 115
- ^ a b Great lives from history. The ancient world, prehistory-476 C.E. Salowey, Christina A., Magill, Frank N. (Frank Northen), 1907–1997. Pasadena, Calif.: Salem Press. 2004. ISBN 978-1587651526. OCLC 54082138.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: others (link) - ^ Lindberg 2007, p. 29.
- ^ a b Algra 1999, p. 57
- ^ Aristotle, Metaphysics, 986b
- ^ a b c Cicero, De Natura Deorum i. 26 (DK 13A10)
- ^ Aristotle, On the Heavens 1.5 411a7-8
- ^ Herbert Ernest Cushman. A beginner's history of philosophy. p. 26.
- ^ a b c "Anaximenes Of Miletus | Greek philosopher". Encyclopedia Britannica. Retrieved 2018-11-30.
- ^ Guthrie 1962, pp. 127–128
- ^ a b c d e Vamvacas 2009.
- ^ Aetius, i. 3, 4 (DK13B2)
- ^ Burnet 1930, p. 73.
- ^ Vamvacas 2009, p. 47
- ^ a b c d Kirk, Raven & Schofield 1957, pp. 152–153
- ^ Guthrie 1962, p. 116
- ^ Vamvacas 2009; Lindberg 2007, p. 29.
- ^ Plutarch, The Principle of Cold, 7 947 F (DK13B1)
- ^ Guthrie 1962, pp. 124–126
- ^ Kirk, Raven & Schofield 1957, p. 146
- ^ Barnes 1982, p. 46
- ^ Peter H. Gommers (2001). What's In A Name. p. 30. ISBN 9789058671493.
- ^ Burnet 1930, p. 77.
- ^ Pseudo-Plutarch, Placita philosophorum 895d
- ^ a b Couprie, Dirk L. (2018), "Peculiarities of Presocratic Flat Earth Cosmology", When the Earth was Flat: Studies in Ancient Greek and Chinese Cosmology, Historical & Cultural Astronomy, Springer, pp. 19–46, Bibcode:2018wewf.book.....C, doi:10.1007/978-3-319-97052-3, ISBN 9783319970516
- ^ a b Aristotle, On the Heavens 294b (DK13A20)
- ^ a b Pseudo-Plutarch, Stromata, 3 (DK13A6)
- ^ Routledge Companion to Ancient Philosophy. Routledge. 4 December 2013. p. 22. ISBN 9781317975502.
- ^ Andrew Gregory (2003). Eureka. p. 24. ISBN 9781840463743.
- ^ Aetius 2.22
- ^ Aetius 2.14
- ^ Eduard Zeller. Outlines of the History of Greek Philosophy. p. 41-43.
- ^ Kočandrle, Radim (2019). "The Cosmology of Anaximenes". History of Philosophy Quarterly. 36 (2): 101–120. doi:10.2307/48563639. JSTOR 48563639. S2CID 246623749.
- ^ Aristotle Meterologica II, 1,354a28
- ^ Graham, Daniel W. "Anaximenes". The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- ^ a b Fairbanks 1898, p. 20-21
- ^ Pseudo-Plutarch, placita philosophorum 888b
- ^ Aristotle Meterologica 2.7 365b6-12 (DK 13A21)
- ^ Guthrie 1962, p. 139
- ^ B. A. G. Fuller (1923). History of Greek Philosophy: Thales to Democritus. p. 98.
- ^ Aristotle, Physics Δ, 6. 213 b 22
- ^ Burnet 1930, p. 79, 108.
- ^ Xenophanes. James H. Lesher (ed.). Fragments. p. 140.
- ^ McKirahan, Richard D. (1994). "Xenophanes of Colophon". Philosophy Before Socrates: An Introduction with Texts and Commentary. Hackett Publishing Company. pp. 65–66. ISBN 978-0-87220-175-0. Retrieved 13 April 2022.
- ^ Burnet 1930, p. 270
- ^ Strabo, Geography, Book 14
- ^ Barnes 1982, p. 26
- ^ Burnet 1930, p. 145.
- ^ Burnet 1930, p. 353–358.
- ^ Graham, Daniel W. (2015-12-30). "Plato and Anaximenes". Études Platoniciennes (12). doi:10.4000/etudesplatoniciennes.706. ISSN 2275-1785.
- ^ Graham, D. (2003). "A testimony of Anaximenes in Plato". The Classical Quarterly. 53 (2): 327–337. doi:10.1093/cq/53.2.327.
- ^ a b Graham, Daniel. The Texts of Early Greek Philosophy. p. 91.
- ^ Phaedo, 99b
- ^ Aristotle, On the Soul, 405a21
- ^ P. J. Bicknell (1966). "TO ΑΠΕΙΡΟΝ, ΑΠΕΙΡΟΣ ΑΗΡ AND TO ΠΕΡΙΕΧΟΝ" (PDF). Acta Classica: 27–48.
- ^ Generation of Animals, 762a18-20
- ^ see Aristotle’s Theory of Material Substance: Heat and Pneuma, Form and Soul by Gad Freudenthal
- ^ Panpsychism in the West by David Skrbina, p. 57
- ^ The Philosophy of Chysippus by Josiah Gould, p. 126
- ^ The Image of the Jews in Greek Literature by Bezalel BarKochva, p. 528
- ^ Theology of the Early Stoa
SourcesEdit
- Algra, K. (1999). "The Beginning of Cosmology". In Long, A. A. (ed.). The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0521446678.
- Barnes, J. (1982). "Science and Speculation". The Presocratic Philosophers. Abingdon: Routledge. pp. 38–56. ISBN 0-415-20351-1.
- Burnet, J. (1930). "Anaximenes". Early Greek Philosophy (4th ed.). London: A & C Black. pp. 72–79.
- Eismann, M. M. (2007). "Anaximenes of Miletus". In Sienkewicz, T. J. (ed.). Ancient Greece: Volume 1. Pasadena: Salem Press. pp. 75–77. ISBN 978-1-58765-282-0.
- Fairbanks, A. (1898). "Anaximenes". The First Philosophers of Greece. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trübner & Co. pp. 17–22.
- Guthrie, W. K. C. (1962). "The Milesians: Anaximenes". A History of Greek Philosophy. Vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 115–139. ISBN 0-521-29420-7.
- Hussey, E. L. (2005). "Anaximenes of Miletus". In Honderich, T. (ed.). The Oxford Companion to Philosophy (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 33. ISBN 0-19-926479-1.
- Kirk, G. S.; Raven, J. E.; Schofield, M. (1957). "Anaximenes of Miletus" (PDF). The Presocratic Philosophers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 143–162. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
- Laërtius, Diogenes (1925). . Lives of the Eminent Philosophers. Vol. 1:2. Translated by Hicks, Robert Drew (Two volume ed.). Loeb Classical Library.
- Lindberg, David C. (2007). "The Greeks and the Cosmos.". The Beginnings of Western Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
- Taran, L. (1970). "Anaximenes of Miletus". Dictionary of Scientific Biography. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons. pp. 151–152. ISBN 978-0-684-10114-9.
- Vamvacas, C. J. (2009). "Anaximenes of Miletus (ca. 585-525 B.C.)". The Founders of Western Thought – The Presocratics. New York: Springer. pp. 45–51. ISBN 9781402097911.
Further readingEdit
- Bicknell, P. J. (1969). "Anaximenes' Astronomy". Acta Classica. 12: 53–85. JSTOR 24591168.
- Classen, C. J. (1977). "Anaximander and Anaximenes: The Earliest Greek Theories of Change?". Phronesis. 22 (2): 89–102. doi:10.1163/156852877X00010. JSTOR 4182008.
- Freeman, Kathleen (1978). Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-03500-3.
- Hurwit, Jeffrey M. (1985). The Art and Culture of Early Greece, 1100–480 BC. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
- Luchte, James (2011). Early Greek Thought: Before the Dawn. London: Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-0567353313.
- Russell, B. (2004). "The Milesian School". A History of Western Philosophy. Abingdon: Routledge. pp. 33–37. ISBN 9780415325059.
- Sandywell, Barry (1996). Presocratic Reflexivity: The Construction of Philosophical Discourse, c. 600-450 BC. Vol. 3. London: Routledge. ISBN 0415101700.
- Stokes, M. C. (1971). The One and Many in Presocratic Philosophy. Washington, DC: Center for Hellenic Studies with Harvard University Press.
- Sweeney, Leo (1972). Infinity in the Presocratics: A Bibliographical and Philosophical Study. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
- Wright, M. R. (1995). Cosmology in Antiquity. London: Routledge. ISBN 9780415121835.
External linksEdit
- Quotations related to Anaximenes of Miletus at Wikiquote
- Anaximenes at the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Anaximenes of Miletus Life and Work – Fragments and Testimonies by Giannis Stamatellos