Vapnik–Chervonenkis theory

(Redirected from VC theory)

Vapnik–Chervonenkis theory (also known as VC theory) was developed during 1960–1990 by Vladimir Vapnik and Alexey Chervonenkis. The theory is a form of computational learning theory, which attempts to explain the learning process from a statistical point of view.

Introduction edit

VC theory covers at least four parts (as explained in The Nature of Statistical Learning Theory[1]):

  • Theory of consistency of learning processes
    • What are (necessary and sufficient) conditions for consistency of a learning process based on the empirical risk minimization principle?
  • Nonasymptotic theory of the rate of convergence of learning processes
    • How fast is the rate of convergence of the learning process?
  • Theory of controlling the generalization ability of learning processes
    • How can one control the rate of convergence (the generalization ability) of the learning process?
  • Theory of constructing learning machines
    • How can one construct algorithms that can control the generalization ability?

VC Theory is a major subbranch of statistical learning theory. One of its main applications in statistical learning theory is to provide generalization conditions for learning algorithms. From this point of view, VC theory is related to stability, which is an alternative approach for characterizing generalization.

In addition, VC theory and VC dimension are instrumental in the theory of empirical processes, in the case of processes indexed by VC classes. Arguably these are the most important applications of the VC theory, and are employed in proving generalization. Several techniques will be introduced that are widely used in the empirical process and VC theory. The discussion is mainly based on the book Weak Convergence and Empirical Processes: With Applications to Statistics.[2]

Overview of VC theory in empirical processes edit

Background on empirical processes edit

Let   be a measurable space. For any measure   on  , and any measurable functions  , define

 

Measurability issues will be ignored here, for more technical detail see.[1] Let   be a class of measurable functions   and define:

 

Let   be independent, identically distributed random elements of  . Then define the empirical measure

 

where δ here stands for the Dirac measure. The empirical measure induces a map   given by:

 

Now suppose P is the underlying true distribution of the data, which is unknown. Empirical Processes theory aims at identifying classes   for which statements such as the following hold:

  • uniform law of large numbers:

     

That is, as  ,

 

uniformly for all  .
 

In the former case   is called Glivenko–Cantelli class, and in the latter case (under the assumption  ) the class   is called Donsker or P-Donsker. A Donsker class is Glivenko–Cantelli in probability by an application of Slutsky's theorem .

These statements are true for a single  , by standard LLN, CLT arguments under regularity conditions, and the difficulty in the Empirical Processes comes in because joint statements are being made for all  . Intuitively then, the set   cannot be too large, and as it turns out that the geometry of   plays a very important role.

One way of measuring how big the function set   is to use the so-called covering numbers. The covering number

 

is the minimal number of balls   needed to cover the set   (here it is obviously assumed that there is an underlying norm on  ). The entropy is the logarithm of the covering number.

Two sufficient conditions are provided below, under which it can be proved that the set   is Glivenko–Cantelli or Donsker.

A class   is P-Glivenko–Cantelli if it is P-measurable with envelope F such that   and satisfies:

 

The next condition is a version of the celebrated Dudley's theorem. If   is a class of functions such that

 

then   is P-Donsker for every probability measure P such that  . In the last integral, the notation means

 .

Symmetrization edit

The majority of the arguments of how to bound the empirical process, rely on symmetrization, maximal and concentration inequalities and chaining. Symmetrization is usually the first step of the proofs, and since it is used in many machine learning proofs on bounding empirical loss functions (including the proof of the VC inequality which is discussed in the next section) it is presented here.

Consider the empirical process:

 

Turns out that there is a connection between the empirical and the following symmetrized process:

 

The symmetrized process is a Rademacher process, conditionally on the data  . Therefore, it is a sub-Gaussian process by Hoeffding's inequality.

Lemma (Symmetrization). For every nondecreasing, convex Φ: RR and class of measurable functions  ,

 

The proof of the Symmetrization lemma relies on introducing independent copies of the original variables   (sometimes referred to as a ghost sample) and replacing the inner expectation of the LHS by these copies. After an application of Jensen's inequality different signs could be introduced (hence the name symmetrization) without changing the expectation. The proof can be found below because of its instructive nature. The same proof method can be used to prove the Glivenko–Cantelli theorem.[3]

Proof

Introduce the "ghost sample"   to be independent copies of  . For fixed values of   one has:

 

Therefore, by Jensen's inequality:

 

Taking expectation with respect to   gives:

 

Note that adding a minus sign in front of a term   doesn't change the RHS, because it's a symmetric function of   and  . Therefore, the RHS remains the same under "sign perturbation":

 

for any  . Therefore:

 

Finally using first triangle inequality and then convexity of   gives:

 

Where the last two expressions on the RHS are the same, which concludes the proof.

A typical way of proving empirical CLTs, first uses symmetrization to pass the empirical process to   and then argue conditionally on the data, using the fact that Rademacher processes are simple processes with nice properties.

VC Connection edit

It turns out that there is a fascinating connection between certain combinatorial properties of the set   and the entropy numbers. Uniform covering numbers can be controlled by the notion of Vapnik–Chervonenkis classes of sets – or shortly VC sets.

Consider a collection   of subsets of the sample space  .   is said to pick out a certain subset   of the finite set   if   for some  .   is said to shatter S if it picks out each of its 2n subsets. The VC-index (similar to VC dimension + 1 for an appropriately chosen classifier set)   of   is the smallest n for which no set of size n is shattered by  .

Sauer's lemma then states that the number   of subsets picked out by a VC-class   satisfies:

 

Which is a polynomial number   of subsets rather than an exponential number. Intuitively this means that a finite VC-index implies that   has an apparent simplistic structure.

A similar bound can be shown (with a different constant, same rate) for the so-called VC subgraph classes. For a function   the subgraph is a subset of   such that:  . A collection of   is called a VC subgraph class if all subgraphs form a VC-class.

Consider a set of indicator functions   in   for discrete empirical type of measure Q (or equivalently for any probability measure Q). It can then be shown that quite remarkably, for  :

 

Further consider the symmetric convex hull of a set  :   being the collection of functions of the form   with  . Then if

 

the following is valid for the convex hull of  :

 

The important consequence of this fact is that

 

which is just enough so that the entropy integral is going to converge, and therefore the class   is going to be P-Donsker.

Finally an example of a VC-subgraph class is considered. Any finite-dimensional vector space   of measurable functions   is VC-subgraph of index smaller than or equal to  .

Proof: Take   points  . The vectors:

 

are in a n − 1 dimensional subspace of Rn. Take a ≠ 0, a vector that is orthogonal to this subspace. Therefore:

 

Consider the set  . This set cannot be picked out since if there is some   such that   that would imply that the LHS is strictly positive but the RHS is non-positive.

There are generalizations of the notion VC subgraph class, e.g. there is the notion of pseudo-dimension. The interested reader can look into.[4]

VC inequality edit

A similar setting is considered, which is more common to machine learning. Let   is a feature space and  . A function   is called a classifier. Let   be a set of classifiers. Similarly to the previous section, define the shattering coefficient (also known as growth function):

 

Note here that there is a 1:1 go between each of the functions in   and the set on which the function is 1. We can thus define   to be the collection of subsets obtained from the above mapping for every  . Therefore, in terms of the previous section the shattering coefficient is precisely

 .

This equivalence together with Sauer's Lemma implies that   is going to be polynomial in n, for sufficiently large n provided that the collection   has a finite VC-index.

Let   is an observed dataset. Assume that the data is generated by an unknown probability distribution  . Define   to be the expected 0/1 loss. Of course since   is unknown in general, one has no access to  . However the empirical risk, given by:

 

can certainly be evaluated. Then one has the following Theorem:

Theorem (VC Inequality) edit

For binary classification and the 0/1 loss function we have the following generalization bounds:

 

In words the VC inequality is saying that as the sample increases, provided that   has a finite VC dimension, the empirical 0/1 risk becomes a good proxy for the expected 0/1 risk. Note that both RHS of the two inequalities will converge to 0, provided that   grows polynomially in n.

The connection between this framework and the Empirical Process framework is evident. Here one is dealing with a modified empirical process

 

but not surprisingly the ideas are the same. The proof of the (first part of) VC inequality, relies on symmetrization, and then argue conditionally on the data using concentration inequalities (in particular Hoeffding's inequality). The interested reader can check the book [5] Theorems 12.4 and 12.5.

References edit

  1. ^ a b Vapnik, Vladimir N (2000). The Nature of Statistical Learning Theory. Information Science and Statistics. Springer-Verlag. ISBN 978-0-387-98780-4.
  2. ^ van der Vaart, Aad W.; Wellner, Jon A. (2000). Weak Convergence and Empirical Processes: With Applications to Statistics (2nd ed.). Springer. ISBN 978-0-387-94640-5.
  3. ^ Devroye, L., Gyorfi, L. & Lugosi, G. A Probabilistic Theory of Pattern Recognition. Discrete Appl Math 73, 192–194 (1997).
  4. ^ Pollard, David (1990). Empirical Processes: Theory and Applications. NSF-CBMS Regional Conference Series in Probability and Statistics Volume 2. ISBN 978-0-940600-16-4.
  5. ^ Gyorfi, L.; Devroye, L.; Lugosi, G. (1996). A probabilistic theory of pattern recognition (1st ed.). Springer. ISBN 978-0387946184.